"The current New Criterion" includes an essay by Gertrude Himmelfarb in which she describes how her evaluation of Edmund Burke as political thinker has improved since she first wrote about him. Burke is sometimes characterized as a reactionary. Himmelfarb:
.... No one could attach that label to the Burke who, as a Whig, not a Tory, sided with parliament and party against the King and his ministers. Nor does it apply to the Burke who was a friend and disciple of Adam Smith, who is reputed to have said that Burke was "the only man who, without communication, thought on these topics [a free economy] exactly as he [Smith] did." Nor does it apply to the Burke who defended John Wilkes, the radical Member of Parliament who was expelled from the House of Commons for libeling the king. Nor to the Burke who conducted a long campaign against Warren Hastings and the East India Company for abusing their charter and exploiting the people of India. Nor to the Burke who joined William Wilberforce in the campaign to abolish the slave trade. Nor, most notably, to the Burke who was an eloquent champion of America before and during the American Revolution.Burke believed that traditions-the habits of a culture-are often the wisdom of generations and that it is foolish to discard them without discovering their origins. Since religion embodies many of those traditions, it is important to society quite apart from its spiritual claims. Human beings are religious creatures and the vacuum created by the absence of religious belief will be filled, often by something very bad indeed. Himmelfarb:
In my early essay, I had quoted derisively his remark "superstition is the religion of feeble minds." But that bald statement is preceded by the warning that an excess of superstition is a "very great evil." And it is followed by the assertion that an "intermixture" of superstition and religion is desirable, "else you will deprive weak minds of a resource found necessary to the strongest." This idea, of an "intermixture" of superstition and religion, seemed to many at the time (as it still seems to many today) demeaning to religion, and, worse, demeaning to those in need of religion-religion "pour les autres", for children, or servants, or others with "weak minds."
As if anticipating that criticism, Burke went on to say that religion is not "a mere invention to keep the vulgar in obedience." On the contrary, it is a "resource" for the "strongest" as well as the weak. Indeed, religion is of the very nature of man: "Man is by his constitution a religious animal." To deprive man of his religion would be to create a void that could only be filled by "some uncouth, pernicious, and degrading superstition," a superstition that would not complement and support religion but rather subvert and degrade it.
As religion and superstition are a part of a continuum, so are reason and prejudice-by "prejudice" he meant not what we mean by it, hostility against particular people or races, but rather all those conventional beliefs and popular opinions that do not meet the strict test of reason. It is in this sense that he spoke of the church establishment as "the first of our prejudices."
We are afraid to put men to live and trade each on his own private stock of reason, because we suspect that this stock in each man is small, and that the individuals would do better to avail themselves of the general bank and capital of nations, and of ages. Thoughtful men [instead of exploding prejudices]... try to discover the latent wisdom which prevails in them, [and] think it more wise to retain the prejudice, with the reason involved, than to cast away the coat of prejudice, and to leave nothing but the naked reason. Prejudice is of ready application in the emergency; it previously engages the mind in a steady course of wisdom and virtue, and does not leave the man hesitating in the moment of decision, sceptical, puzzled, and unresolved. Prejudice renders a man's virtue his habit; and not a series of unconnected acts. Through just prejudice, his duty becomes a part of his nature.This was an audacious idea to present to enlightened men in an enlightened age-a challenge to those French philosophes who would indeed leave men with nothing but their "private stock of reason," their "naked reason." It was all the more audacious because Burke's continuum of reason and prejudice-prejudice with the "reason involved," with the "latent wisdom" in it-had the effect of creating a commonality among human beings. It was the "common feelings," the "natural feelings" of men, the "wisdom of unlettered men," that permitted him to speak so confidently of "the true moral equality of mankind." [more]Anyone interested in political theory will find the essay instructive.